The paper is about risk taking and self-command. It was written for a
philosophy class in ethics.
The title of the paper is “Risk Taking”. It recieved 95 points out of a
possible 100.
Risk Taking
In our lives, it is important to exercise self-command. However,
we should not be so concerned with the future that we stifle the present.
The question becomes what balance should we strike between self-command
and risks? What kinds of risks are acceptable or unacceptable? In this
essay, we will use two examples of risks to show the distinction between
the two and arrive at a conclusion as to the balance one should have
between risk and self command. The first example we will use is of a
person who spends his life savings on a lottery ticket and does not win
the lottery. The second is of a person who spends his life savings on a
hunch regarding a cure for AIDS, a hunch that is false. Before we make
this distinction, however, it is necessary to define the terms acceptable
and unacceptable risks.
Acceptable and Unacceptable Risks
There are several ways in which one could define which risks are
acceptable. One could say, for example, that the only acceptable risk is
The Essay on Risk and Major Life Undertakings
An adventure is an exciting or unusual experience. It may also be a bold, usually risky undertaking, with an uncertain outcome. [1]Adventures may be activities with some potential for physical danger such as skydiving, mountain climbing,river rafting or participating in extreme sports. The term also broadly refers to any enterprise that is potentially fraught with physical, financial or ...
one for which the odds of success are greater than the odds of failure.
Another definition of acceptable risk might be a risk that does not harm
one’s future. We might also say that the only acceptable risk is one
where the aggregate happiness is increased, thus increasing the moral good
of the risk, an idea which is based on John Stuart Mill’s Utilitarianism.
Finally, we might define a morally good risk in a Kantian way by saying
that the only acceptable risk is one which is rationally thought out
(Thomas, lecture).
Now that we have several definitions of acceptable risks, we may
ask how these definitions, which seem piecemeal and unrelated, can all
combine to form one definition of acceptable risk. The best way to do
this is to examine the two cases that lie before us and relate the
definitions to them. In the process of doing so, we will determine which
risk is acceptable and which is not.
Risks in the example: the lottery and the AIDS cure
If the average person on the street were presented with the case
of spending one’s life savings on a lottery ticket and losing or spending
the same sum on a false hunch regarding an AIDS cure, he or she would
probably come up with several answers. For the most part though, all the
answers would be consistent with one idea: the AIDS cure is simply
“worth” more and thus is a more acceptable risk. There might be several
reasons for this. One could assume, for example, that the only person who
would attempt to cure AIDS would be a doctor with sufficient experience in
the field. It would follow, then, that the odds of finding a cure for
AIDS would be much greater than the odds of winning the lottery. To win
the lottery, one has to draw 6 numbers out of 46 (a probability that is
very low).
However, curing AIDS with medical experience is a less risky
endeavor. In this instance, trying to cure AIDS would be a greater moral
The Essay on AIDS Epidemic Increase And African Countries Economies
The countries of the developing world most seriously affected by AIDS thus far are in sub-Saharan Africa. Accordingly, much of the social research on AIDS in the developing world is concerned with Africa, as is much of the research reviewed in this chapter. But many of the behavior patterns described and the conclusions reached apply elsewhere. AIDS is primarily a sexually transmitted disease, and ...
good because it is less risk involved in it than in trying to win the
lottery. This case, although quite valid, is not very interesting. In
fact, we have solved it rather rapidly. The more interesting case, and
the one we will consider in depth here, is the case in which one has no
medical experience whatsoever, but still attempts to find a cure.
Furthermore, we will set the odds such that one has a better chance of
winning the lottery than finding a cure for AIDS. Yet, I will still
show that, regardless of the greater chance of failure, the attempt at an
AIDS cure is still has more moral worth than the purchase of the lottery
ticket, even though both result in failure.
Why does the spending one’s life savings on an AIDS cure have more
moral worth (which makes it a more acceptable risk) than spending the same
sum on a lottery ticket, when the numerical odds of being successful are
the same? Why bother, since in the end, the result is the same? The
answer lies in Mill’s definition of a moral good, that which is done to
increase the common happiness (Mill, Utilitarianism).
The AIDS cure is something that will increase the common happiness, while
a person winning the lottery generally will only increase his or her
happiness. This is almost obvious. Certainly, if I was to win the
lottery, I would increase my happiness greatly, but the increase in the
general happiness would be negligible. However, if I were to find a cure
for AIDS, it would greatly increase the general happiness. Masses of
suffering people and their loved ones would be much happier. Even though
my attempt was unsuccessful, it would still be greatly appreciated. Just
the thought of a cure would have given hope to what could otherwise be a
bleak existence. The mere possibility of being saved from an almost
certain death would increase several victims’ happiness. We see this
today, when, each time a new drug that delays the progression of AIDS is
approved, people flock to it. That such things are not cures and that
The Term Paper on Some Dark Thoughts On Happiness Analysis
Jennifer Senior discusses her research concerning positive psychology and whether or not happiness is teachable and highlights some of the darker sides of happiness. To start the article, Senior reveals her score on her test from the Authentic Happiness Inventory. The test designed by Chris Peterson of the positive Psychology Center at the University of Pennsylvania. This test is intended to ...
some of them do not offer guarantees (indeed, many are experimental) is
almost insignificant. People still try them. Why? Because they offer a
hope of continuing what humans treasure most: life. Similarly, my AIDS
cure would offer some hope to patients who are assured an eventual long,
painful death. Maybe the cure might work for them. If not, that it did
not would be almost insignificant. Spending my life’s savings on an AIDS
cure would almost certainly increase the general happiness, as it would
provide hope. That, in the end, it is a failure is of little, if any,
significance.